Bernard Rollin's newest book, A New Basis for Animal Ethics: Telos and Common Sense, set against a fantastic feature wall (alas, not mine). |
When one considers the staggering amount of unnecessary suffering experienced by animals in all the multifarious uses we impose upon them, it is virtually impossible to remain unmoved” – Bernard Rollin, 2016.
There is no question that our society is predicated on
animal use which is almost impossible to escape. The food we eat, the clothing
we wear, the medications we rely on, are based to a large extent on animals.
For philosopher and ethicist Bernard Rollin, the problem is not with animal use
per se but the suffering that this causes in various contexts.
He's not the only person to raise concerns about the use
of animals. Others like Peter Singer have argued that we have a moral duty to
minimise (or eliminate, where possible) suffering. This reflects a utilitarian
approach – seeking to maximise good, or pleasure, and minimise pain. Then there
are people like Tom Regan who take a rights-based approach, arguing that we
should respect the rights of animals just as we have learned to respect the
rights of other groups in society, for example women.
Many ethicists get caught up in a debate about whether
there are morally relevant differences between people and animals, which may or
may not “compel us to withhold the full range of our moral machinery from animals,”
Rollin writes in his latest book, A New Basis for Animal Ethics: Telos and Common Sense.
What we need to pay
attention to, he argues, is the telos or nature of animals.
“As Aristotle pointed out, living beings have unique strategies for solving the problems inherent in living – sensing, moving, reproducing, nourishing themselves – the thwarting of which matters to them…Telos allows us to talk of animal interests…well beyond the narrow restrictions of pleasure and pain. In addition, it provides an excellent shield against the sorts of rationalisations that confinement agriculturalists, in particular, have given in defence of keeping animals in highly restrictive and impoverished environments. They tend to argue that in confinement systems, animals do not need to worry about finding food, extremes of climate, predators – all needs are supplied by the system. While there is certainly some truth in this argument, it neglects the fact that animals are built to, for example, find food in certain ways.” p55
According to Rollin, then, animals have needs and desires
which flow from their natures or teloi, which – when thwarted, frustrated or
unmet – lead to negative feelings or the experience of poor welfare.
Acceptable systems of animal use, Rollin argues, must
accommodate the telos of the animals involved. In other words, to have a life
worth living, animals must be able to express the full suite of natural
behaviours. Rollin’s arguments are compelling and his examples – drawn from
decades working with veterinarians and others trying to improve the lot of
animals in contexts ranging from laboratory animal medicine to agriculture –
are fascinating.
My interpretation is that Rollin calls for a return to
more extensive, traditional husbandry systems (as opposed to intensive
agriculture) and – where the benefits of experimentation are shown to outweigh
the costs – laboratory animal housing that accommodates the specific needs of
species and individuals involved. He doesn’t really discuss companion animals,
but he does talk about domestication. He argues that domestication and in fact
genetic engineering do not violate telos, because it is not the nature of
animals that is sacred and inviolable – rather the interests flowing from it.
As he writes, “It is a better world in which husbandry
and sustainability reign over productivity and profit at all costs. The animals
live decent, natural lives. Animal welfare is integral to the system, not an
afterthought to be politically imposed” (p128).
Though he concedes this will be challenging, Rollin
argues we don’t have much choice.
“…we must consider that industrial agriculture is very likely living on borrowed time, not being inherently sustainable. If, for example, we lose cheap energy, the whole system collapses” (p129).
Rollin’s approach relies on us to observe, recognise,
respect and protect the interests of animals. If we are going to use animals
for our own ends, he argues, we must ensure they have a “good” life.
This book provides a good overview of Rollin’s work, a
fascinating history of animal welfare science and the animal rights movement,
and a good discussion of some of the limitations of traditional ethical
approaches. Like all philosophy books, it raises many questions, including how
we legislate protection of telos.
Definitely a must-read for those who are interested in
the ethics of animal use.
Reference
Rollin BE (2016) A New Basis for Animal Ethics: Telos and
Common Sense. University of Missouri Press, Columbia.